"BLACK BOXES' the overt manifestation of the covert
Dr. Ariella Atzmon
July
2003
Copyright © Ariella Atzmon, â¤*2003
All Rights Reserved
One can own a mirror; does one then own the reflection that
can be seen in
it?
Zettel: 670
The relevance of this Wittgenstein remark (Zettel sec:717),
hints at the
rhetorical language of propaganda used in the course of contemporary
democracy and its links to false images of science implanted in
the public
consciousness in the course of contemporary science education.
With reference to recent political events following the September
11th
disaster, let me examine the use and abuse of the â¤"Black
Box⤠terminology.
The expression â¤"Black Boxâ¤
crops-up whenever it is necessary to elucidate an
enigmatic event by transforming the covert into an overt clear-cut
exposition. As related to the airplane crash in Queens NY on the
12th of
November 2001, the report of that event might reveal a device
for the
subversion of peopleâ¤s minds. We should ask:
how is it possible that the
people of NY were so easily convinced in just two hours, that
the event was
an accident and not another terrorist attack? The fact is that
the moment
the announcement on finding the 'magic' Black Box (claimed to
consist of
ultra- digital information technology) was made, all the news
channels
suddenly replaced this news item with reports of the invasion
of Kabul by US
troops.
What is meant by a Black Box? Does it signify the urge to decipher
something in order to achieve transparency, or does it specify
an opaque
entity, its content doomed to remain unknown?
The maneuvering of the notions imposed on the 'Black Box' metaphor,
originates in philosophical behaviorism representing a locked,
opaque
object - impenetrable to any snooping, inquisitive investigation.
All the
in-put/out-put (stimuli/response) conditioning that triggered
the
sophistication of Nazi propaganda brain-washing is grounded in
this
behaviorist notion of Black Boxes.
The â¤"Black Box⤠terminology
entered the philosophic vocabulary in relation
to the Carnap Skinner debate around the status of theoretical
terms[1]. The
behaviorist argument asserts that since theoretical terms links
initial
input observable entities with output factual data, it is possible
to skip
the theoretical framework, as represented by a â¤"Black
Box.⤠Hence, reality
is supervised as an efficient summation of evidential reports,
as long as it
meets the requirement for predictions and explanations. This view
enables to
keep up with a descriptive methodology, releasing the reporter
from
referring to the contextual meanings in use.
Thus, cynically, the same â¤"Black Boxâ¤
nowadays simultaneously portrays an
opaque entity beside a transparent key for unveiling information.
This
covert/overt ambiguity provides a rhetorical mechanism for the
disclosure of
something that might be lost and is aimed at enhancing peoplesâ¤
trust that
things are firmly under control.
Rhetoric in the course of Liberal democracy manifests a
positivist-behaviorist approach that complies with the truth theory
of
correspondence, i.e. associating a name to a thing. It links a
term to sense
data in order to ratify meanings by using a rule of correspondence.
An alternative mode for validation of statements is to distance
ourselves
from observable attributes, interpreting a term by coherence criteria
-
where a meaning is understood in the terminology of relationship
and
difference.
Education can be seen as a key for implanting the correspondence
theory of
truth as all-inclusive. Most recent educational programs are lacking
a
serious engagement with an abstract theoretical terminology. Contemporary
education is a bizarre blend of two rival philosophical movements
namely;
positivism and phenomenological constructivism. The efforts invested
in
instructing students to construct reality in terms of their own
experience
are blurred between Husserelian phenomenology and Positivist-
behaviorism.
While the first stresses genuine expression alongside the experiencing
of
pure phenomena, the second view advocates rigorous methodological
conduct
for the articulation of descriptive reports. The uncontrolled
zealous
devotion to the experiencing of solid factual data reveals the
educationistâ¤
s ignorance. Educational programs can be seen as a â¤"Hailing
process⤠where
the student is told â¤follow me, I am about to teach
you how to construct
your own reality.â¤*
Confidence in factual data is rooted in the Lockian Ideational
Theory of
Meaning referring to language as representation. Representational
thinking
treats reality as if it were a picture "placed before"
the subject.
Fallacious images of scientific thought describe language as a
'vocabulary
of things.⤠According to this view, communication
is enabled since words
signify ideas in a perceptible way. Consequently language is essentially
a
tool for the interaction between human minds. Hence, our thoughts
are
viewed as an amplification of sequential ideas that associate
a vocal sound,
giving it the same meaning. The link between our minds and the
objects
which are perceived by our senses, is mediated by the process
of name
giving.
The ideal of sharing a similar interpretation of the same linguistic
sign
concurs with techno-scientific language. This language authorizes
the use of
linguistic signs as clear-cut signals, narrowing the multiplicity
of
expressive utterances, making way for the most determined communicative
descriptions or reports. The techno-scientific language gains
its power due
to education systems governed by scientism[2]. Education, that
operates as a
selective membrane for the meaning in use protects the social
order by
signalizing the linguistic sign.
The Freudian-Lacanian idea that what has not acquired meaning
can never be
known reveals a vicious circle, where the rhetorical game signalizes
meanings. The scientific cover-up allocated to findings, grasped
as clusters
of factual data formulating a suitable basis for rational reasoning,
is
connected to the citizenâ¤s self-image in democratic,
liberal society.
Consequently the rhetorical representation of signalized, scientific
language becomes part of an ideological illusion of freedom of
choice.
Thus, the liberal promise of emancipation is related to human
beings as
individuals whose rational abilities grant them the ability to
judge, choose
and plan their life-style competently in the framework of democratic
life.
Planting positive attitudes in favor of a system where given data
serve as
the basis for legal, moral and ethical judgments raises individual
illusion
regarding freedom of choice. In the western, liberal democratic
milieus it
is agreed that calculative thought, based upon well-established
punctuated
evidence, is preferential upon personal impressive verbalization.
The weight
bestowed in advance on digital descriptions considered to be legitimized
reports is based on an arbitrary linguistic contract. Hence, the
more the
scientific façade of a statement is enhanced, the
more its authorization is
recognized. A hegemonic approach to language as correspondence
(i.e.;
representation) defines MEANINGS in terms of what should be included
or
excluded under a specific term. The political conclusion is that
the promise
of modernity for self-realization, including some postmodernist
hopes for
emancipation, are mediated by an a-priori tendency to signalize
the sign.
The prestigious status of scientific thought, spurred an obsessive
drive in
the philosophy of science to demarcate between the scientific
and the
non-scientific (Popper). The necessity for demarcation preserves
the
criteria for what is considered valid and what should be thrown-out
as
meaningless. â¤"Credibleâ¤
information amasses its authority via science images
that proliferate in liberal societies, namely: referring science
exclusively
to organized factual knowledge. The compulsive occupation with
the problem
of demarcation reflects a struggle for control over the legitimization
of
specific modes of information. Popular acceptance of the positivist
images
of science is reflected in the media, in the courts, in achievement
assessments, in I.Q. testometry and so on.
Science is self-maintained via narrow definitions of rationality
which
relate judgments to a link between a concept and its experiential
attributes. But in order to examine whether something can be considered
â¤"rational,⤠one must utilize
the concept of rationality invented by the
selfsame designers of the same widespread science images. This
may be
compared to a situation where the police investigate itself. I
would say
that the same approach that plants the illusion of free choice,
simultaneously blocks the possibility for emancipation.
My argument can be clarified by the illustration of a final
pre-election TV.
confrontation between the main rival candidates. That style of
interview
with the trickery rhetorical sound bites in a ping-pong game,
dictates a
race where the opponents⤠statements are restricted
to no more than ten
seconds at the most. The question is: â¤how is the
process of rhetoric
designed, so that what a politician is unable to say on TV in
a sound bite
of three minutes, he will never get a second chance to speak about
at large?
One may describe pre-second world war rhetoric as a deductive
Euclidean
inference relying upon axiomatic assumptions, keeping within the
bounds of
coherence. In contrast to those styles, postwar western rhetoric
presents us
with a sort of T.V. â¤espressoâ¤* style,
defined by Arthur Koestler as â¤"short,â¤
â¤"instant⤠and â¤"concentrated.â¤
The politician, with the aid of P.R.
companies, will succeed as long as he blends, briefly in one gulp,
the
proper ingredients in the right dose, so that he may be simultaneously
convincing, pleasant, and sufficiently vague to cover as many
people as
possible under the same umbrella. So, information is not just
what is coming
out of the T.V. screen, but those corresponding algorithmic modes
of
reasoning which pave the way to how we listen to the news.
By choosing a substantial word (such as evil, or terror) and
charging it
with a univocal meaning, optimal obscurity is achieved
Identification of the indicators of a successful rhetorical
blend presents
to us the subtle role of education that disappears from view precisely
because of its importance. It is education that fixates the false
images of
science, which support the rules for how science should be presented
to the
public.
By using Lyotardâ¤s terminology of the â¤"Differendâ¤
I argue that the victims
of science images are unable to make a claim against scientism,
because
there is a latent web of rules which imposes shared agreement
about â¤"what
science means.⤠I propose that not only is
education itself safeguarded
within the patterns of scientism, but also that education fortifies
scientism, establishing a self-maintaining system by the dissemination
of
its power.
The distinctiveness of western propaganda is founded upon the
fact that both
liberalism and the scientific revolution came into the world arm-in-arm.
The
main characterization of western propaganda is that latent commitment
to
support pervasive statements by well-established, evidential proof.
Actually, all those I-philosophies (from Descartes to Husserl)
that stress
that human rational ability can facilitate a close correspondence
between
the realm of abstract meanings and the realm of reality as perceived
by the
senses, have supported and protected liberal democracy ever since.
Taking the Heideggerian stance regarding the human subject
as being shaped
by language rather than by his mind and his personal experience,
undermines
the human self-image as an individual empowered with the capability
of
rational free choice. Since the concept of individuality is the
cornerstone
of liberal democracy, Heideggerian philosophy endangers the whole
texture of
the western rhetorical machine. Heideggerâ¤s
view of language as the â¤"home of
being⤠affords us an innovative gaze into
the route taken by propaganda for
trapping peoples⤠minds in the webs of the
hegemonic discourse.
In the name of â¤scientific neutralityâ¤*,
scientism confuses science with
technology, and thereby the definitions for â¤rationality,â¤*
and â¤objectivityâ¤*
are narrowed. This is how liberal democracy becomes entangled
with scientism
by virtue of the praise given to human, calculative, sovereign
reasoning.
But this reasoning illusion is manipulated by the behaviorist
approach that
treats the human mind as a Black Box, conditioned by the stimuli/response
procedure. In other words, in this way kidnapped meanings, which
correspond
with overt, evidential reports, replace scary covert warning alerts.
I
assert that this subversive manipulation of human minds is an
unethical act.
It is another version of brain washing in the framework of liberal
democracy, which even more intensifies the gap between calculative
reasoning
and ethical judgment.
Lyotard titled â¤"the Differendâ¤
as â¤the case of conflict between two parties
that cannot be equitably resolved for lack of a rule of judgment
applicable
to both arguments.â¤* The â¤" Differendâ¤
illustrates precisely the logic of the
dominance of discourses that are relied upon, and at the same
time support
experiential evidence. As such, it marks a point of incommensurability.
Scientism is typical of genres which attempt to increase harmonious
consonance by ignoring alternative discourses that confront us
with an
absence of rules for a clear-cut judgment. The legal system, in
the course
of liberal democracies, relates to harm assessments and evidential
proof in
order to validate statements. But, there is no simple viable route
for moral
or ethical proof. Even if there are rules for what should be described
as
judgment, they are inaccessible because of their ethical nature.
When the
issue at stake is justice, legality, which has to do with the
complications
of statutes, belongs to a calculative culture, so it needs proofs,
supported
by factual evidence, but for moral judgment there are no simple
proofs.
In the course of the liberal paradigm, the variety of interests
and
traditions necessitates a state apparatus accepted by all. Secular
liberalism established the civil legal system as an all-embracing
means for
stabilization, the resolution of conflicts and the legitimization
of its
rule. Thus, in liberal regimes, rhetoric turned from being concerned
with
how politics is supposed to cope with ethics, into trickery, an
instrumental
maneuver attempting to find the means by which to adjust the law
to
politics. According to the utilitarian approach, ethics became
a calculative
apparatus for the assessment of harm caused by the â¤"evil
other.⤠Liberal
democracy put a barrier between morality and ethics on the one
side and
legality on the other. Even the notion of the word innocence as
related to
terror(ized) victims is weighed in accordance with the ideological
affiliation of the victims. In reference to Israeli spokesmen,
democratic
civilian victims are innocent compared with Palestinian kids (always
killed
by mistake).
Liberal democracyâ¤s obsession with evidential
proof in pursuit of the
validation of statements ends with disregard for ethical judgment.
Contrary
to the doctrines of legality, the ethical judgment cannot be learned,
neither cannot it be taught. The ethical judgment must be exercised,
â¤for
more we judge the better we judgeâ¤* However escape
from the rhetoric of the
referent involves misery, agitation, and insomnia. (Lyotard).
To endorse the
proofs provided by â¤"smoking gunsâ¤
in favor of insomnia becomes the turning
point where people start to behave like restless night watchmen,
who stay
alert to the vicious abuse of language.
There is relief in the act of philosophizing â¤even
though one is not a
philosopher. The populist current view referring to reality as
a â¤"vocabulary
of things,⤠i.e.: representation, prevents
an encounter with the sublime.
The â¤"Black Box⤠propaganda
style blocks the ability to contemplate vague
positions that entail doubts and uncertainties. Thus, the citizens
of
liberal democratic countries are left defenseless as an easy prey
in the
hands of a subversive- persuasive rhetoric.
Faith in clusters of data presented by â¤"Black
Boxes⤠expertise leads to
civic irresponsibility and alienation. I would say that despite
the song of
praise to â¤"democracyâ¤
we are likely to find ourselves withdrawing to the
pre-democratic era!
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
----
[1] The behaviorist argument which was pointed out by B. F.
Skinner in
Science and Human Behavior (1953), was elaborated by Carl Hempel
as the
Theoreticianâ¤s Dilemma.â¤
[2] By â¤"scientismâ¤
I mean an excessive belief in the power of scientific
knowledge and techniques, as well as a belief in the applicability
of the
methods of the physical sciences to other fields, especially human
behavior
and the social sciences.